Adorno and the autonomy of art
Andy Hamilton
Durham University
·
Adornoʼs unique brand of Western Marxism, in which the ideals of art for artʼs sake and absolute music remain salient, presents a complex and elusive treatment of the autonomy of art, which it is the task of this article to examine. It may seem puzzling how any kind of Marxist could believe in the autonomy of art. Autonomy is normally taken to mean that art is governed by its own rules and laws, and that artistic value makes no reference to social or political value. 1 Autonomy is taken to oppose the economic conditioning of culture assumed by classical
Marxism. However, Western Marxism questioned the base/superstructure model, and Adornoʼs version of it offers the subtlest account of that relation.2 It is a mark of the perspicacity of Adornoʼs treatment that he was able to do justice both to the social situation of art and music, and to their autonomy status – indeed he did justice to each through the other. Adorno delineates the functionlessness of art, and its social situation in virtue of that functionlessness. For Adorno, autonomous artworks have a social situation but – as I will put it – no direct social function: “Insofar as a social function may be predicated of works of art, it is the function of having no function”.3 That is, autonomous art has as its “purpose” the creation of something without direct purpose or function – pre-bourgeois art such as religious or theatre music, in contrast, does have a direct social function.
Another way of putting this claim is to say that autonomous art constitutes an autonomous practice that does not serve any other practice. That is, it is an end in itself – just as religious practice is also autonomous and lacks direct social function. Adornoʼs picture is that as the artist became free of church and aristocratic patronage towards the end of the 18th century, their work simultaneously
Bibliography: Adorno, T. (1976), Introduction to the Sociology of Music, trans. E. Ashton, New York: Continuum International Publishing Group. ——————- (1997), Aesthetic Theory, trans R. Hullot-Kentor, London: Athlone. Attali, J. (1985), Noise: Political Economy of Music, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Banham, R. (2001), Los Angeles: The Architecture of Four Ecologies, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Bernstein, J. (2004), “Adornoʼs Aesthetic Theory”, in F. Rush ed. The Cambridge Companion to Critical Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004, pp. Bourdieu, P. (1987), Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste, trans Brady, E. and Levinson, J., eds. (2001), Aesthetic Concepts: Essays After Sibley, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Bürger, P. (1998), “Autonomy: Critique of Autonomy”, in Kelly ed. (1998). Clunas, C. (1997), Art in China, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Folgarait, L. (1998), Mural Painting and Social Revolution in Mexico, 1920-1940: Art of the New Order, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Fubini, E. (1991), The History of Music Aesthetics, trans. M. Hatwell, London: Macmillan. Geuss, R. (2005), “Art and Criticism in Adornoʼs Aesthetics”, in his Outside Ethics, Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp Goehr, L. (1992) The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Goffen, R. (2004), Renaissance Rivals: Michelangelo, Leonardo, Raphael, Titian, Yale: Yale University Press. Hamilton, A., (2007), Aesthetics and Music, London: Continuum. ———————— (forthcoming 2008), “Mill, and Elitism: Classical liberalismʼs response in the rise of democracy”, in E Helm, P. (1971), “Function”, Philosophical Quarterly, pp. Hobsbawn, E. (1982) The age of Revolution 1789-1848, London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson. Jarvis, S. (1998), Adorno: A Critical Introduction, Oxford: Polity. —————- (2004), “Adorno, Marx, Materialism”, in Huhn ed. (2004). Jay, M. (1984), Adorno, London: Fontana. Kelly, P., ed. (1998), Encyclopedia of Aesthetics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lavine, T. (1965), “Karl Mannheim and Contemporary Functionalism”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 25:4, pp Merton, R. (1949), “Manifest and Latent Functions”, in his Social Theory and Social Structure, Glencoe: Free Press Turner, J., and Maryanski, A. (1988), “Is ʻNeofunctionalismʼ Really Functional?”, Sociological Theory, 6:1, pp.110-121. Uglow, J. (2002), Hogarth: A Life and a World, New York: Farrar Straus Giroux. Wolff, C. (2000), Johann Sebastian Bach: The Learned Musician, New York: W. Zangwill, N. (2001), “Aesthetic functionalism”, in Brady, E. and Levinson, J., eds. (2001), pp. 123-48. Zuidervaart, L. (1990), “The Social Significance of Autonomous Art: Adorno and Bürger”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 48:1, 61-77. 1 See for example Geuss (2005), p. 161. 2 Bernstein (2004), p. 142. 3 Adorno (1997), p. 227. Here, it is understood that “work of art” = “autonomous work of art”. 4 As Zuidervaart puts it, for Adorno, “the autonomy of the work has a social character and the social character of the work is itself autonomous” (Zuidervaart (1990), p 5 Bernstein (2004), p. 146. 6 Bernstein (2004), p. 146. 7 Geuss, in his otherwise persuasive (2005), seems to be led into this misinterpretation through neglect of non-formalist features of Kantʼs aesthetics; for instance, “autonomy and formalism are not a priori properties of all art and of all artistic experience, as Kant thought” (p. 178). Haskins (1989) rightly comments that Kant “never speaks of art…as autonomous in the third Critique” (p 9 Constant makes the first recorded use of “art for artʼs sake” in 1804 – see Haskins (1989), p. 52 n2, and Hamilton (2007), Ch is pursued in Hamilton (2007), Ch.3. 11 Hobsbawn (1962), p. 325. 12 Holsbawrn (1962), p. 325. 13 Discussed further in Hamilton (2007), and (in preparation). 14 Wilde (1909), p. 54. 15 Hamilton (2007) and (in preparation). 16 Adorno (1997), p. 194. 17 Adorno (1997), p. 5. 18 Adorno (1997), p. 146. 19 As Berger (1997) notes, p. 6. 20 Attali (1985), p. 47. 21 Zuidervaart (1990), p. 68. Geuss distinguishes a “sociological” thesis about whether art is established in a certain society as a distinct form of human endeavour, from a thesis about the evaluative criteria for art ((2005), p. 161n).