Preview

Geach's Argument

Powerful Essays
Open Document
Open Document
1414 Words
Grammar
Grammar
Plagiarism
Plagiarism
Writing
Writing
Score
Score
Geach's Argument
In this paper, I will present the arguments of two philosophers about the definition of “good”. First, I will present Moore’s argument that “good” is indefinable. Then, I will present Geach’s response to this and how he can undermine Moore’s argument. Next, I will discuss in what sense Geach believes “good” can be defined. Finally, I will discuss my opinion on who has the correct definability of “good” and give reasons to defend my opinion. Moore sets the groundwork by first defining the province of ethics. He proposes the question, what is common and peculiar to all ethical judgements? He offers a suggestion that “what is good or bad in human conduct” will be the answer to this. He refutes this, however, based on the fact that good conduct …show more content…
Moore notes that there are different senses of the question “what is good in general”. In one case, something distinct is being judged and the question “what is good” is answered by “this”. Moore says that this cannot be the correct sense to view the question because “ethics does not deal with facts that are unique, individual, or absolutely particular” (Moore $3). Another sense to view the question “what is good in general” is by answering “what” by classes of good things. You could answer the question by saying food is good, but this would be false. It may be true that many types of food are good, but some food is bad. Moore proposes that the question “what is good” may have another meaning. We may mean to ask not what thing or what things are good, but rather how is good to be defined. Moore concludes that this must be the fundamental question of ethics, since that which is meant by good is the only simple object of thought peculiar to ethics (Moore $5). Now that the fundamental question …show more content…
Geach explains that there are two different kinds of adjectives, predicative and attributive. In a phrase “X is an AB”, A being an adjective and B being a noun, “A” is predicative if the phrase splits logically into “X is A” and “X is B”. “A” is attributive if the phrase does not logically split into “X is A” and “X is B” (Geach 34). For example, take the phrase “Sam is a small whale”. The adjective “small” is attributive because the phrase does not logically split into “Sam is small” and “Sam is a whale”. Sam could be a small whale but a big animal, therefore this is illogical. To determine whether “good” is predicative or attributive, take for instance the phrases “a blue boat” and “a good boat”. You could determine that an object far away in the ocean is a blue boat by observing that the object is blue and that the object is a boat. However, you cannot determine that a distant object is a good boat by observing that the object is good and that it is a boat. This shows that “good” is an attributive adjective, not predicative. Geach says there is no such thing as being just good, there is only being a good thing. X can be a good boat but X cannot simply be good. Moore’s claim that good is indefinable relies on the premise that “good” is a predicative adjective, or in other words,

You May Also Find These Documents Helpful

  • Good Essays

    Moore attacks the naturalist perception of moral values, particularly in the naturalist definition of “good”. He argues that the word “good” is indefinable and is explained in his “open question argument”. This argument suggests that any definition should result in a closed question. For example, a bachelor is defined as an unmarried man therefore making it a closed question to ask whether a certain bachelor is unmarried, as the answer would only and always be yes. This question is a tautology and therefore a closed question. The same cannot be said of the proposition “all bachelors are ugly” because it leads to an open question, since the answer could be yes or no. this is because the meaning of ugly is not contained within…

    • 1002 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Better Essays

    “What makes something good or bad… is the basic norms of goodness and badness are part of the moral code of…

    • 990 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Good Essays

    The ambiguous line between “good” and “bad” is prevalent in the novel, Haroun and the Sea of Stories. Haroun is a young boy in the book, and with that comes an innocence and a rather unbiased view towards adult topics such as the good and evil. In the beginning, Haroun is heavily influenced by the light side of his world. When he runs into the “evil” beings located on the other side of his world, he is initially very afraid of them.…

    • 838 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    In What Is Good and Why: The Ethics of Well-Being, Richard Kraut argues against a “conative” conception of the good. According to him, this view is attractive because it emphasizes the satisfaction of desires and volitions, giving agents “a starring role to play” in creating their own good (114). The conative theory proposes that when an agent (rationally) desires something, that thing is good for them precisely because it is the object of their desire (or conation) (118). A proponent of this view might accept that sometimes we ought to desire an object because it will prove good for us. However, they will maintain that other times, even if the object is not intrinsically “worth wanting,” it is good for us in virtue of being what we desire (118).…

    • 599 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    The following analysis deals with the nature and source of evil and whether, given our innate motives and moral obligation, we willingly choose to succumb to our desires or are slaves of our passion. From this argument, I intend to show that our human nature requires that we play into our desires in order to affirm our free will. This is not to say that our desires are necessarily evil, but quite the opposite. In some sense, whatever people actually want has some relative value to them, and that all wanted things contain some good. But given that there are so many such goods and a whole spectrum of varying arrangements among them, that there is no way we can conceive anything as embodying an overall good just because it is to some degree wanted by one or a group of persons. In this light, there arises conflict which can only be resolved by a priority system defined by a code, maybe of moral foundations, which allows us to analyze the complexities of human motivation. I do not intend to set down the boundaries of such a notion, nor do I want to answer whether it benefits one to lead a morally good life, but rather want to find out how the constructs of good and evil affect our freedom to choose.…

    • 3607 Words
    • 15 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Better Essays

    Contemporary philosophers such as, G.E. Moore, C.L. Stevenson, and J.L. Mackie, all have theories that develop different views concerning the status of moral judgments and the existence of moral facts. Moore, in his, Subject Matter of Ethics, argued that moral facts do exist and can be true or false but must be indescribable. Stevenson, in his, The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms, disagreed with Moore and said that moral judgements can’t be true or false they simply can inspire certain feelings of approval or disapproval in humans. Mackie, in his, The Subjectivity of Values, would disagree with both and say that there are no moral facts and that all moral judgments are simply wrong. It seems to be the case, on soundness alone, that Moore has…

    • 1566 Words
    • 7 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    First, we divulge in the exploration of Kant’s normative ethical theory. The basis of the Kantian ethical theory is that acts, and the intentions behind those acts, are what makes an outcome good over bad. Kantianism divides this theory into three ways to determine intentions behind acts; “universal law”, and the “formula of humanity”. These two imperatives being the most widely discussed here on out.…

    • 1520 Words
    • 7 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    Aristotle's Virtue Ethics

    • 1763 Words
    • 8 Pages

    Name: Title: Supervisor: Date: Introduction Ethics, otherwise called good theory, is an extension of reasoning that includes arranging, shielding and embracing ideas of good and bad lead. The super field inside reasoning known as axiology incorporates both morals and style and is brought together by every sub-limb's worry with quality. Philosophical morals examines what is the most ideal path for people to live, and what sorts of activities are correct or wrong specifically circumstances (Mappes & DeGrazia, 2001).…

    • 1763 Words
    • 8 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Good Essays

    Moore establishes that “pleasure is not the sole good” (PE, 146). He says, “right,” means nothing but “cause of a good result” (PE, 147). By this claim, Moore asserts that the end always justifies the means and that an action cannot be bad if it produces a good result. In other words, what is morally “right” is an action, which causes the greatest good in the universe than any other possibility (PE, 148). For example, if we say that there’s no such case that murder could produce the greater good in the universe, then we are declaring that it is a duty not to murder.…

    • 1364 Words
    • 6 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Friedrich Nietzsche’s first essay, The Good and Evil, Good and Bad is Nietzsche’s thoughts on the concepts of ‘good’ and ‘evil’. In describing the origins of ‘goodness’, Nietzsche points out that the concept of ‘good’ was created when an individual determined “un-egoistic” acts to be “good” (Nietzsche, §2). Furthermore, the idea of a ‘good’ act came from the point of view to which the deeds were done. However, he does not agree with this origin of “good”. Rather, he argues that “good” had not been determined by those who were shown goodness, but by those who see themselves as “the good”—the noble man (§2).…

    • 852 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    It acknowledges that decisions about “proper” and “wrong” may be hard, and can be related to character context. It first offers a summary of the fundamental sources for ethical wondering, after which affords a framework for decision-making. For instance: If a person is…

    • 999 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    In this paper, I will argue on the argument which is about proving that every action that gets us what we want is good and that all good actions are moral. This argument is not a sound argument. This is because the conclusion of the argument on morality is not supported by the premises. The argument fails to define what is good and what is moral, that morality is not all about what is good for us but is good for others, and that there are also actions that get us what we do not want.…

    • 1138 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Better Essays

    Immanuel Kant Morality

    • 1319 Words
    • 6 Pages

    A critic who believes that the quality of the will must be in some way related to the intention or consequences of an action challenges the fundamental deontological aspect of Kant’s thinking; consequentialists and the like have no place in Kant’s argument unless they are prepared to unravel Kant’s philosophy on basic morality first. In the case of criticisms denouncing the idea of absolute good or not good in wills, Kant – very simply – does not believe in a necessity to justify such criticisms. Qualitative goodness is not the issue in Kant’s argument; just to do good is to fulfill of the natural purpose of reason, and it is far too early or presumptuous of any philosopher to deem goodness accordingly to separate calibers or degrees of excellence. In the context of Kant’s argument, absolute good and not good are values that do not pose a problem for rational coherency – although it is true that Kant does not address the immediate discomfort moral constraints impose on the agent, as rational coherency is his foremost priority. However, Kant does address the problems of unanticipated imposition of happiness, which is, to reiterate, the sum of an agent’s inclinations.…

    • 1319 Words
    • 6 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Good Essays

    tries to judge a piece of beauty; Ethics address goodness – whether what we are doing is…

    • 3133 Words
    • 13 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    qualifying adjective

    • 361 Words
    • 2 Pages

    There are only a very small number of exceptions, notably concerned involved, present and responsible, which have a particular meaning when they come after a noun. There are also some cases in which old and tall follow the noun…

    • 361 Words
    • 2 Pages
    Good Essays