The two aspect view provides its own solutions to the two world view's problems. Since the two aspect view shifts the focus from a metaphysical distinction to one concerning the conditions of human knowledge, Berkeleyian empirical idealism …show more content…
can be avoided. This is because appearance is no longer associated with representation but with the thing in itself (Robinson 419). Appearances and things in themselves are two different ways of considering, rather than two distinct entities; the consideration of something as a thing in itself is simply discursively necessary to consider it as an appearance (Robinson 421). The spatiotemporal problem can also be solved by this account. Space and time are conditions of possibility for our experience of things, rather than conditions of possibility of things in themselves (A1 11). This avoids the dilemma by avoiding a nonspatial, nontemporal element effecting a spatial, temporal element. Other benefits of the two aspect view includes the ability for Kant to explain the folly of his predecessors and the allowance for human beings to be considered things in themselves (Robinson 416). Thus Allison establishes a solid solution to the problems of the two world interpretation.
Robinson believes that Allison's two aspect view has a lack of textual support. Allison's position is predicated on the notion that the appearance is not identical with the representation; it must coincide with things in themselves. One problem is that the great deal of the text seems to
support the two world thesis; the appearance is identical with the representation (Robinson 419). In the antimony of pure reason, Kant clearly defines appearances as mere representation (A2 111). Robinson argues that Allison has the burden of proof; he must show textual support for his notion that things in themselves coincide with reprepresentation rather than show that arguments against this notion are lacking (422). Robinson holds that Kant's original work does not support Allison's two aspect view.
The second problem that Robinson has with Allison's interpretation is that one object seemingly possesses two different aspects. The two aspect view seemingly applies that the same object can be considered both spatially and nonspatially and this is clearly absurd. If Allison's consideration of an object under an aspect is to be considered as nonvacuous, there must be a sense in which the object posses those aspects (Robinson 422). A Buick can be considered as many different things, but one would be mistaken to consider it as a horse or a river. This leads to the obvious question of an object possessing two different aspects that are entirely contradictory.
Robinson argues that Allison must take the filtration model as the only possible relationship between subjective representations and their objects (Robinson 423).
Allison seemingly embraces the filtration model. In this model, things in themselves are the result of certain ontological conditions, which are completely independent of representations (Robinson 423). Epistemic conditions "filter out" things lacking representation enabling features and then filters those that are not shared with others (Robinson 424). If representations do not depend upon objects than epistemic conditions may not necessarily lead to objects; this would lead to a version of empirical idealism (Robinson 423). If objects only exist because they meet …show more content…
epistemic
conditions then ontological and epistemic conditions are the same thing (Robinson 423). Thus, Robinson concludes that Allison's only viable route is the filtration model.
Robinson argues that the filtration model leads to a variety of new problems. The first is known as the isomorphism problem; every object that appears must have an in-itself aspect (Robinson 425). The underlying thing in-itself aspect would be individuated by spatiotemporal characteristics; this is entirely against the nonspatiality of things in themselves (Robinson 425). The filtration model presuppose that a nonvacuous methodological distinction assumes a likewise distinction for the object (Robinson 426). Any object that survives the filtration process must have both an in-itself aspect and an an-appearance aspect; this leads to either a repetition of one object possessing two objects or a repetition of the two world view (Robinson 427). This filtration model leads to a variety of problems with the two aspect view.
Allison makes many counterarguments against Robinson's critiques. He responds to the lack of textual support by positing not that spatiotemporal entities have no existence, simply that they have no mind independent existence (A2 112). Robinson mischaracterizes Allison's position in his argument against him. Allison disagrees with the conception that mere appearances are equivalent to things in themselves as this would constitute a form of transcendental realism (A2 112). Allison holds that the debate between idealism and realism is a meta-epistemological one rather than a merely metaphysical or epistemological one (A2 114). The transcendental realist holds that human beings could somehow have access to a nondiscursive, intellectual intuition about how things even are; even skeptical empiricists such as Berkeley, still implicitly appealed to this paradigm (A2 114). What makes transcendental idealism unique is that it rejects the sort of paradigm that Robinson argues that it is victim to. The epistemic conditions reflect the structure of the mind, rather than the mind's relationship to a pregiven reality (A2 115).
Specifically, the epistemic conditions reflect the normative conditions that necessitate metaphysical and ontological claims in the first place. Robinson thus fails to grasp Allison's argument when he posits his ontological criticism of Allison. Allison emerges relatively unscathed from Robinson's attacks.
The two perspective view holds that appearances and things in themselves are the result of differing perspectives rather than objects or considerations. The predominant distinction between the two perspective model and the two aspect model is that the epistemic conditions and ontological conditions are equivalent for the former (Robinson 429). In this account, the appearance of the object is found within the anthropocentric view, while the thing in itself is within the theocentric view (Robinson 428). According to this account, at the empirical, at the empirical level these appearances are taken to be real, it is only once I enter the transcendental level that these appearances are doubtable (Robinson 429).
The anthropocentric world view has greater ontological significance in the two perspective view.
The divine perspective ultimately derives from the human one; it is created to serve human needs (Robinson 431). We can only think of what the divine perspective might look like as there is no way to escape it (Robinson 431). This theocentric perspective is conjured up only as a result of reflecting on the limitations of our own human perspective (Robinson 431). We are trapped in the human perspective; even our understanding of God's perspective is done through the human perspective (Robinson 431). Only due to the possibility of error are we capable of moving to the divine and thinking of the object as empirically real yet transcendentally ideal (Robinson 439). The "real" for human beings constitutes the best picture that we have within the human perspective, there is nothing that is more real in which to
contrast
it (Robinson 440). The two perspective view demands a priority to the anthropocentric perspective.
The two perspective view holds itself capable of solving the problems of the two world view without running into the supposed problems of the two aspect view. Robinson manages to avoid the collapse into Berkeleyan empirical idealism. While the object can only exist due to representations, they are not identical with them (Robinson 429). Rather, the case is that the appearance is an intentional object generated through the representation (Robinson 429). Furthermore, the two perspective view rejects the assumption that the object arises at the same time as when it is constituted; objects can be constituted in the mind long after they have left (Robinson 435). The two perspective view solves the problem of spatiality by holding that not every object of appearance needs an individuated in-itself object of appearance (Robinson 435). Since the in-itself perspective and the as-appearance perspective are not parallel and do not exist independently, spatiality can apply to appearances without applying to the unknown in-itself perspective (Robinson 435-436). Thus the two perspective view manages to provide coherent problems to the two perspective view without falling into the supposed problems of the two aspect view.
Allison critiques this viewpoint by arguing that Robinson's viewpoint is completely contrary to Kant's transcendental idealism. The main problem is that the theocentric perspective is one which Kant abandoned in his critical philosophy (2Allison 120). Allison argues that Robinson's position is a transcendental realist one; as the theocentric perspective reflects how things "really are" (2Allison 122). This remains true even when God's perspective is construed as (2Allison 122). Furthermore, Robinson gives ontological privilege to appearances by making things-in-themselves subsequent to them; this further undermines the spirit of the critical
philosophy. Allison saliently argues that the two perspective view is against the Kant's conception of philosophy.
The two aspect view is the best position for dealing with the difficulties of the two world view while avoiding any serious difficulties of its own. The two world and two perspective views lead to insurmountable problems that motivate their destruction. Kant introduced a paradigm shift that changed the nature of philosophy entirely; the two aspect view best expresses this. It is the only position that gives Kant the historical and philosophical relevance that he rightly deserves; it makes the best of the transcendental turn. ,The two aspect view really does rebirth transcendental idealism as a coherent and revolutionary system of thought.