Top-Rated Free Essay
Preview

How far, if at all, can analogies with machines help us to assess theories of the relationship between mind and body?

Good Essays
1688 Words
Grammar
Grammar
Plagiarism
Plagiarism
Writing
Writing
Score
Score
How far, if at all, can analogies with machines help us to assess theories of the relationship between mind and body?
How far, if at all, can analogies with machines help us to assess theories of the relationship between mind and body?

Physicalism is the view that everything that exists is physical, or depends on something that is physical. For a physicalist, the mind is not a substance or a thing. It is more accurate to talk of mental properties, mental events, mental states and processes. We can then say that these properties (etc) are possessed not by a mind, but by a person or brain, which are physical objects. In short, mental states are brain (physical) states, says the type identity theorist. Therefore, thinking a thought or feeling an itch is exactly the same thing as certain neurones firing.

This explicit relationship between mental and brain states, however, seems too confined. Hilary Putnam provides an objection to type identity theory saying that mental properties cannot be identical to physical properties because the same mental property can be realised by different physical properties. Type identity theory is not multiply realisable. For instance, the type identity theorist may say that being in pain is C fibres firing. According to Putman, this cannot be the case since the brain states that relate to pain are different in different species, but pain is still the same mental property. Therefore, ‘being in pain’ cannot be exactly the same thing as being in any one of these different physical states (C fibres firing) because a squid can have the mental state ‘being in pain’ even though it does not have C fibres. Thus, type identity theorists are guilty of chauvinism.

Token identity theory agrees that mental states are physical events, but rejects the claim that mental properties are identical to physical properties, thus, avoiding criticism from Putnam’s argument from multiple realisability. Instead, token identity theory maintains that while mental properties are not identical to physical properties, each individual occurrence (‘token’) of a mental property is identical with the occurrence of a physical property. So, the mental property ‘being in pain’ is not identical with any physical property i.e. C fibres firing, however, each time the mental property ‘being in pain’ occurs in a particular creature, it occurs with and because of the occurrence of some physical property. In a different creature or on a different occasion ‘being in pain’ may occur with and because of another physical property e.g. D fibres firing. Nevertheless, this mental property only ever occurs with and because of the occurrence of some physical property. By avoiding the problem of multiple realisability, token identity theory can be said to be a better theory of the mind than type identity theory. However, this leaves us with the problem that no brain state need correspond to any sort of mental state or behaviour whatsoever. This cannot even be tested for, since it may be argued that we can never have the same thought twice and, therefore, never the same brain state. Even though this criticism does not disprove the theory, it means that there is nothing to suggest beyond doubt that brain states are mental states. Though it is highly liberal, it seems that it is better to side with token identity theory than it is to side with type identity theory.
Functionalists did just that. Functionalism is usually understood to be a token identity theory, in that functionalism agrees that brain states are responsible for mental states, but disagrees that they are identical with them. For functionalists, mental states are states that exist between input, such as a stimulus experience, and output, such as behaviour. To characterise a mental state, we need to describe its typical inputs and outputs. Therefore, we can say that mental states are functional states.
The property of ‘having function x’ is a property that can occur in many different physical things. For example, ‘being a mousetrap’ is a functional property. There are several different mousetraps, built in different ways, using different methods and materials. Likewise, ‘being in pain’ is also a functional property, in that there are a lot of different physical ways, different brain states that could be ‘being in pain’. This might not just vary from species to species; it could vary from one individual to another, or even in one individual, from one time to another.
To help understand this idea, consider the usual functionalist example of a computer. Imagine that you ask a computer to add the numbers 3 and 7. On one level - at a low level - what is happening in the computer is dependent on the hardware; on another level - a high level - the computer's software is calculating the answer. Since, historically, computers have had different hardware that works in different ways; we cannot describe the process of calculation as the activity of hardware. Instead, the functionalist argues, the process of calculation is simply realised by the hardware. Therefore, the software is a function of the hardware. So, in terms of the brain, mental states are dependent upon brain states or neurological activities in the same way that the functions of a computer program are dependent upon computer hardware. With this computer model, brain states are analogous to the hardware and mental states to the software. Functionalists say that brain states help to realise mental states and that the mind is, in fact, a total functional system. By this, they mean that a mind is made up of the total possible functional (mental) states that it can have and that these interact with the inputs and each other in order to produce outputs or behaviour.
The functionalists’ use of a computer model which describes the mind as a multiply realisable total functional system lends itself to arguments for Artificial Intelligence (AI). AI is a research project in computer science that aims to create computers that display behaviour that is intelligent. Some philosophers and scientists argue that a test for whether a computer is intelligent is the ‘Turing Test’. A person, a computer and another person (the interrogator) are each in a different room. The person puts the same questions, in turn, to the person and computer, not knowing which is which. If, after five minutes, the interrogator cannot tell from his conversations with the person and computer which is which, then the machine has passed the Turing Test.
Whether the Turing Test is a good test for intelligence is very controversial. Some say that all the test really does is expose how little we know about what makes people people. The fact that it's easy to deceive people into thinking a computer is human doesn't actually teach you anything about the difference between computers and humans; we still feel as if there is something more to humans. Some say that the something that computers lack is consciousness, they cannot be genuinely intelligent.
John Searle argues that Intentionality is not reducible to functions. Many mental states are ‘about’ something, objects or events in the world. For example, I might have a belief about Paris, a desire for chocolate, be angry at the government, or intend to go to the pub. In all of these cases, my state of mind is directed towards and object, the thing I am thinking about. This idea of directedness is known as Intentionality. To illustrate his argument, Searle describes a room with two holes in the wall; through one, pieces of paper are passed in (inputs), through the other, pieces of paper are passes out (outputs). There is someone in the room who has to respond to the inputs by sending the outputs. The inputs are questions in Chinese; the person doesn’t understand Chinese, but has a rule book which correlates every question with an answer. The person finds the output that is that answer, and sends the piece of paper out. The room as a whole- a system- ‘behaves’ as if it understands Chinese. But it doesn’t; the person doesn’t, the rulebook doesn’t, the room doesn’t. Even if the person memorised the rulebook, he wouldn’t understand Chinese, says Searle. The person would not know what the questions mean. Searle argues that this is what real Intentionality requires. Yet the room performs the same functions as someone who does understand Chinese. So performing functions isn’t enough for understanding meaning, for real Intentionality.
Some functionalists have rejection Searle’s conclusion: the room does understand Chinese. To illustrate their point, functionalists develop Searle’s thought experiment: the person inside the room is replaced by a computer that does the same thing. Suppose we then put the computer inside a robot, which interacts with the world. We add a programme for correlating visual input (through a camera in its eye) to output. So, the robot is now capable of naming things in Chinese, as well as answering questions in Chinese. Functionalists ask if it is still obvious to conclude that the robot doesn’t understand Chinese.
Searle would still say that it doesn’t. Artificial intelligence isn’t intelligence at all; at best it is a simulation of intelligence. The Chinese room performs the function that a human would perform. Likewise, other computers demonstrate a range of mind capacities such as monitoring and controlling bodily processes, purpose, logical thought, memory, the ability to learn and so forth. However, although, the simulation of Intentionality is convincing, Searle maintains that there if a distinct difference between authentic Intentionality and the simulated kind. This difference is consciousness. Without consciousness, a series of functional interactions remain meaningless to the robot, or computer, even though they look meaningful to us. But intentional states are meaningful from the inside: they are meaningful to the creature that has them.
Though analogies with machines cannot help us to assess theories of the relationship between mind and body since machines appear to lack consciousness and consequently intentionality, they do highlight the similarities in which humans and computers produce certain outputs. For example, most people perform long division by following rules, where the only intentional aspect if knowing that the rules will provide the answer to a question about how many times one answer ‘goes into’ another.

You May Also Find These Documents Helpful

  • Good Essays

    It is very difficult to attribute characteristics to a mind when we know it does not actually exist in the physical realm. Though, personal identity has been connected to the mind. However, it is tricky to determine what exactly comprises one’s personal identity. Although it is a difficult concept to grasp, philosophers such as Nagel and Chisholm attempt to construct their own position on the characteristics of the mind. By comparing Nagel and Chisholm’s positions on personal identity, it is evident that identity is a development of both body and mind. Nagel shows that we cannot properly identify a mind, and if this is the case then it is impossible to attribute personal identity to a mind. In turn, he attacks the idea that personal identity can be defined in terms of physical attributes. Chisholm shows that although things are constantly changing, they still remain the same. He argues that it is the mind that holds our identity, regardless of physical alteration. In my view, the physicalist perspective of identity is the most logical when contrasted to the mentalist argument simply due to the fact that we do have a self-identity, and Nagel does not attempt to define what it is. Locke’s argument finds a middle ground between Nagel and Chisholm as he argues for a conscious and bodily continuity of the mind.…

    • 1610 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    For example, the mind provides functions such as thinking, doubting, hating, or desiring. In contrast, the body or brain are mere physical extensions, and simply represent how a person is shaped or the color of their skin. The body and brain do not provide contributions to the mental functioning of a being, and simply provide a physical platform under which the mental, and its own capacities of thought and contemplation, may be housed. As an extension, all things in the universe may be qualified as a body, a physical entity, or a mind, a thinking entity. Additionally, a mind does not need a body to provide it shelter, and regardless of ever having a body, a mind will exist for eternity because it lacks the characteristics of a physical entity, which cause it to degenerate. In conclusion, Substance Dualists perceive the mind and body as separate and distinct substances due to their unique abilities and…

    • 616 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    The view of interest here holds to the objection that personal identity is anything but ubiquitous, but rather the set of characteristics in question form a personality, which a person merely possesses as a holding, a constitutive of personal consciousness. On this view, a person can change their personality without having their identity annihilated in the strict sense implied by Hume, because one’s personality as well as the personality traits is constitutive of personal identity. Based on how this idea has been refined in recent paragraphs, I propose we rename it personality as a constitutive of personal identity or personality as a constitutive for short. The basis for personality as a constitutive has been that personal identity as a static…

    • 330 Words
    • 2 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Better Essays

    When we consider psycho-physical identity statements about the mind and body, theoretically they should be analogous to type-identity statements in the external world. For instance when we discover that water is H2O, when presented with evidence, we do not feel inclined to ask why this is the case. However even after ample scientific evidence that pain is in fact c-fibres firing, we would still tend to raise questions as to why pain feels this certain way and not any other way. This impression that despite sufficient physical knowledge the relation is still unexplained is precisely what Levine points out in “Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap”.…

    • 1060 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Good Essays

    Epiphenomenalism Analysis

    • 565 Words
    • 3 Pages

    It is sometimes claimed that a physicalist picture of the mind entails an epiphenomenalist view; Thomas Huxley gives an introduction to this idea in his book On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata (1874/2002):…

    • 565 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    The accounts for personal identity, thought up by John Locke, were skeptical for several philosophers throughout time. Locke believes that we are the same person as we were yesterday because of our personal identity. He says that our personal identity is founded on consciousness namely, a continuity of conscious memories, but that the substance of the soul or body does not affect our personal identity. First, I will discuss what Locke believes to be a person. Second, I will explain why Locke believes personal identity has to be a continuous consciousness throughout time. Third, I will asses Thomas Reid's objection to Locke's account on personal identity and explain why I believe Reid's account is stronger.…

    • 1152 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    As a human beings we have beliefs, desires, emotions and other ‘mental states’; and our bodies seems to react to those mental states; for instance, if believe that Wynton Marsalis will play a show, I will move my body to get the tickets before they sell out. From the completeness of the physics we know that those mental states are physical; but nonetheless, the question remains as to how to explain those mental states in physical terms? The identity theory as a first approach has been problematic, but it is not totally wrong in the sense that mental states depend upon a physical base – a brain state – the problem is that reductive methodology is prone to the criticisms of Putnam and Fodor. These…

    • 762 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    Australian Materialism

    • 1888 Words
    • 8 Pages

    As mentioned above the materialist perspective adopted by Smart urges us to see identity theory like any other common theoretical identification in science. While smart understands that it is difficult for science to articulate events such as sensations he believes that as essentially everything can be described through science, it is “frankly unbelievable” (Armstrong, 142, 1968) that an explanation of sensations cannot be deductively reached through science. Smart, makes a clear distinction in his explanation of sensations as brain processes and that is, that it is not his hypothesis that sensations, or “reports of sensations such as “aches”, mean the same as brain process X (where X is a brain process)(Smart, 144, 1959). More specifically he elaborates an ache is a report of a process that happens “to be a brain process” (Smart, 144, 1959). These sensations statement that we experience, such as aches and pains, or his preferred example of a orange after image are thus merely reports of something occurring and that something is in fact a brain process. When a person says ‘I see a yellowish-orange after-image’ (Smart, 141, 1959) he is saying something like this: "There is something going on which is like what is going on when I have my eyes open, am awake, and there is an orange illuminated in good light in front of me" (Smart, 149, 1959). In explaining his theory on identity, Smart explores a range…

    • 1888 Words
    • 8 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Good Essays

    Miss

    • 1088 Words
    • 5 Pages

    2. Physicalism, also known as Materialism, states that everything that exists is ultimately physical. According to the Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (published 2001) "Physicalism is the thesis that everything is physical, or as contemporary philosophers sometimes put it, that everything supervenes on, or is necessitated by, the physical." Coined by Otto Neurath in the early twentieth century in a series of papers, it is stated that "According to physicalism, the language of physics is the universal language of science and, consequently, any knowledge can be brought back to the statements on the physical objects." (Keith, J.F 2010). With regards to the mind-body problem, a physicalist would argue that responses and thoughts are purely mechanisms of the brain i.e., chemical reactions through neurotransmitters across synapses leading to an equally physical response.…

    • 1088 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    He agrees that identity is a bundle of memories or perceptions; meaning that they all interconnect; or that these perceptions “succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement” (2). It is hard to maintain and to say that one is exactly in that personality forever because he is always changing…

    • 1005 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    The Mind-Body problem

    • 1454 Words
    • 4 Pages

    Many theories have been challenged throughout the history of psychology. Mind vs. Body is one of the most important issues that has formed the basic foundation in this field today. One of the central questions in psychology and philosophy concerns the mind-body problem: Is the mind part of the body, or the body part of the mind? If they are distinct, then how do they interact? And which of the two is in charge? (McLeod, 2007). Philosophers have examined the relationship between the two and have proposed a variety of approaches to support their arguments.…

    • 1454 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    the most important arguments in the philosophy of mind. Physicalism is the metaphysical thesis that, basically, everything in this world-including cars, humans, animals, research papers, even our sensations-are ultimately physical. The knowledge argument attempts to refute this thesis by appealing to the following made-up scenario known as “Mary’s Room”:…

    • 1300 Words
    • 6 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Best Essays

    Theory of mind

    • 2466 Words
    • 10 Pages

    predictions about how others will behave, according to the state of mind they are presumed to be in.…

    • 2466 Words
    • 10 Pages
    Best Essays
  • Better Essays

    putnam

    • 1258 Words
    • 6 Pages

    The next part of Putnam’s Twin Earth argument claims that if our standard of psychological difference is what is in the head, there can be no psychological differences between the speakers of both worlds. If this is true, we must then redefine the traditional concepts of meaning that have been defined by other philosophers. As of now, there are two unchallenged assumptions of the theory of meaning. The first being, “ knowing the meaning of a term is just a matter of being in a psychological state”and the second being, “the meaning of a term determines its extension”.…

    • 1258 Words
    • 6 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Good Essays

    Mind Body Debate

    • 614 Words
    • 3 Pages

    Philosophers have been debating for centuries the relationship between the mind and the body and whether they are separate entities, or if they are one. This is known as the mind/body problem. If the mind being our consciousness and the body being our brain is separate parts, do they relate to each other or work together? If they are one, do they depend on each other? The idea that the mind and body are one is called monism. The idea that the mind and body are separate is called dualism (Newall, 2005).…

    • 614 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays

Related Topics